Aristotelianism

Aristotle, by Francesco Hayez

Aristotelianism (pronounced /ɛərɨstəˈtiːljənɨzəm/) is a tradition of philosophy that takes its defining inspiration from the work of Aristotle. The works of Aristotle were initially defended by the members of the Peripatetic school, and, later on, by the Neoplatonists who produced many commentaries on Aristotle's writings. In the Islamic world, the works of Aristotle were translated into Arabic, and under philosophers such as Al-Kindi, Al-Farabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, Aristotelianism became a major part of Early Islamic philosophy. Although some knowledge of Aristotle's logical works was known to western Europe, it wasn't until the Latin translations of the 12th century, that the works of Aristotle and his Arabic commentators became widely available. Scholars such as Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas interpretated and systematized Aristotle's works in accordance with Christian theology.

Contents

History

Ancient Greece

The original followers of Aristotle were the members of the Peripatetic school, which derives its name from the ancient Greek word peripatetikos, which means "of walking" or "given to walking about". Aristotle's school came to be so named because of the peripatoi ("colonnades" or "covered walkways") of the Lyceum gymnasium where the members met.[1] The most prominent members of the school after Aristotle were Theophrastus and Strato of Lampsacus, who both continued Aristotle's researches. After this time the school concentrated on preserving and defending his work.[2] The most important figure in the Roman era is Alexander of Aphrodisias who commentated on Aristotle's writings. With the rise of Neoplatonism in the 3rd century, Peripateticism as an independent philosophy came to an end, but the Neoplatonists sought to incorporate Aristotle's philosophy within their own system, and produced many commentaries on Aristotle.

Islamic world

In the Abbasid Empire, many foreign works were translated into Arabic, large libraries were constructed, and scholars were welcomed.[3] Under the caliphs Al-Ma'mun and his son Harun al-Rashid, the House of Wisdom in Baghdad flourished. Christian scholar Hunayn ibn Ishaq (809-873) was placed in charge of the translation work by the caliph. In his lifetime, Ishaq translated 116 writings, including works by Plato and Aristotle, into Syriac and Arabic.[4][5] Al-Kindi (801-873) was the first of the Muslim Peripatetic philosophers, and is known for his efforts to introduce Greek and Hellenistic philosophy to the Arab world.[6] He incorporated Aristotelian and Neoplatonist thought into an Islamic philosophical framework. This was an important factor in the introduction and popularization of Greek philosophy in the Muslim intellectual world.[7]

The philosopher Al-Farabi (872-950) had great influence on science and philosophy for several centuries, and was widely regarded to be second only to Aristotle in knowledge (alluded to by his title of "the Second Teacher") in his time. His work, aimed at synthesis of philosophy and Sufism, paved the way for the work of Avicenna (980-1037).[8] Avicenna was one of the main interpreters of Aristotle.[9] The school of thought he founded became known as Avicennism, which was built on ingredients and conceptual building blocks which are largely Aristotelian and Neoplatonist.[10]

At the western end of the Mediterranean Sea, during the reign of Al-Hakam II (961 to 976) in Cordoba, a massive translation effort was undertaken, and many books were translated into Arabic. Averroes (1126-1198), who spent much of his life in Cordoba and Seville, was especially distinguished as a commentator of Aristotle. He often wrote two of three different commentaries on the same work, and some 38 commentaries by Averroes on the works of Aristotle have been identified.[11] Although his writings had only marginal impact in Islamic countries, his works would eventually have a huge impact in the Latin West,[11] and would lead to the school of thought known as Averroism.

Europe

Although some knowledge of Aristotle seems to have lingered on in the ecclesiastical centres of western Europe after the fall of the Roman empire, by the ninth century, nearly all that was known of Aristotle consisted of Boethius's commentaries on the Organon, and a few abridgments made by Latin authors of the declining empire, Isidore of Seville and Martianus Capella.[12] From that time until the end of the eleventh century, little progress is apparent in Aristotelian knowledge.[12]

The renaissance of the 12th century saw a major search by European scholars for new learning. James of Venice, who probably spent some years in Constantinople, translated Aristotle's Posterior Analytics from Greek into Latin in the mid-twelfth century,[13] thus making the complete Aristotelian logical corpus, the Organon, available in Latin for the first time. Scholars travelled to areas of Europe that once been under Muslim rule and still had substantial Arabic-speaking populations. From central Spain, which had come under Christian rule in the eleventh century, scholars produced the many of the Latin translations of the 12th century. The most productive of these translators was Gerard of Cremona,[14] (c. 1114-1187), who translated 87 books,[15] including many of the works of Aristotle, including his Posterior Analytics, Physics, On the Heavens, On Generation and Corruption, and Meteorology. Michael Scot (c. 1175-1232) translated Averroes' commentaries on the scientific works of Aristotle.[16]

Aristotle's physical writings began to be discussed openly, and at a time when Aristotle's method was permeating all theology, these treatises were sufficient to cause his prohibition for heterodoxy in the Condemnations of 1210-1277.[12] In the first of these, in Paris in 1210, it was stated that "neither the books of Aristotle on natural philosophy or their commentaries are to be read at Paris in public or secret, and this we forbid under penalty of excommunication."[17] However, despite further attempts to restrict the teaching of Aristotle, by 1270 the ban on Aristotle's natural philosophy was ineffective.[18]

William of Moerbeke (c. 1215-1286) undertook a complete translation of the works of Aristotle or, for some portions, a revision of existing translations. He was the first translator of the Politics (c. 1260) from Greek into Latin. Many copies of Aristotle in Latin then in circulation were assumed to have been influenced by Averroes, who was suspected of being a source of philosophical and theological errors found in the earlier translations of Aristotle. Albertus Magnus (c. 1200-1280) was among the first among medieval scholars to apply Aristotle's philosophy to Christian thought. He produced paraphrases of most of the works of Aristotle available to him.[19] He digested, interpreted and systematized the whole of Aristotle's works, gleaned from the Latin translations and notes of the Arabian commentators, in accordance with Church doctrine. His efforts resulted in the formation of a Christian reception of Aristotle in the Western Europe.[19] Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), the pupil of Albertus Magnus, wrote a dozen commentaries on the works of Aristotle.[20] Thomas was emphatically Aristotelian, he adopted Aristotle's analysis of physical objects, his view of place, time and motion, his proof of the prime mover, his cosmology, his account of sense perception and intellectual knowledge, and even parts of his moral philosophy.[20] The philosophical school that arose as a legacy of the work of Thomas Aquinas is known as Thomism, and was especially influential among the Dominicans, and later, the Jesuits.[20]

Modern era

After retreating under criticism from modern natural philosophers, the distinctively Aristotelian idea of teleology was transmitted through Wolff and Kant to Hegel, who applied it to history as a totality. Although this project was criticized by Trendelenburg and Brentano as un-Aristotelian, Hegel’s influence is now often said to be responsible for an important Aristotelian influence upon Marx.[21] Postmodernists, in contrast, reject Aristotelianism’s claim to reveal important theoretical truths.[22] In this, they follow Heidegger’s critique of Aristotle as the greatest source of the entire tradition of Western philosophy.

Contemporary Aristotelianism

Aristotelianism is understood by its proponents as critically developing Plato’s theories.[23] Recent Aristotelian ethical and ‘practical’ philosophy, such as that of Gadamer and McDowell, is often premised upon a rejection of Aristotelianism’s traditional metaphysical or theoretical philosophy. From this viewpoint, the early modern tradition of political republicanism, which views the res publica, public sphere or state as constituted by its citizens’ virtuous activity, can appear thoroughly Aristotelian.

The most famous contemporary Aristotelian philosopher is Alasdair MacIntyre. Especially famous for helping to revive virtue ethics in his book After Virtue, MacIntyre revises Aristotelianism with the argument that the highest temporal goods, which are internal to human beings, are actualized through participation in social practices. He opposes Aristotelianism to the managerial institutions of capitalism and its state, and to rival traditions—including the philosophies of Hume and Nietzsche—that reject its idea of essentially human goods and virtues and instead legitimate capitalism. Therefore, on MacIntyre’s account, Aristotelianism is not identical with Western philosophy as a whole; rather, it is "the best theory so far, [including] the best theory so far about what makes a particular theory the best one."[24] Politically and socially, it has been characterized as a newly 'revolutionary Aristotelianism'. This may be contrasted with the more conventional, apolitical and effectively conservative uses of Aristotle by, for example, Gadamer and McDowell.[25] Other important contemporary Aristotelian theorists include Fred D. Miller, Jr.[26] in politics and Rosalind Hursthouse in ethics.[27]

See also

Notes

  1. Nussbaum, M. (2003), "Aristotle", page 166, in Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony, The Oxford Classical Dictionary (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press; Furley, David (2003), "Peripatetic School", page 1141, in Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony, The Oxford Classical Dictionary (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press; Lynch, J. (1997), "Lyceum", page 311, in Zeyl, Donald J.; Devereux, Daniel; Mitsis, Phillip, Encyclopedia of Classical Philosophy, Greenwood Press
  2. Furley, David (2003), From Aristotle to Augustine: Routledge History of Philosophy, 2, Routledge
  3. Wiet. Baghdad
  4. Opth: Azmi, Khurshid. "Hunain bin Ishaq on Opthalmic Surgery." Bulletin of the Indian Institute of History of Medicine 26 (1996): 69-74. Web. 29 Oct. 2009
  5. Lindberg, David C. The Beginnings of Western Science: Islamic Science. Chicago: The University of Chicago, 2007. Print.
  6. Klein-Frank, F. Al-Kindi. In Leaman, O & Nasr, H (2001). History of Islamic Philosophy. London: Routledge. p 165
  7. Felix Klein-Frank (2001) Al-Kindi, pages 166-7. In Oliver Leaman & Hossein Nasr. History of Islamic Philosophy. London: Routledge.
  8. "Avicenna/Ibn Sina (CA. 980-1137)". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/a/avicenna.htm. Retrieved 2007-07-13. 
  9. "Avicenna (Abu Ali Sina)". Sjsu.edu. http://www.sjsu.edu/depts/Museum/avicen.html. Retrieved 2010-01-19. 
  10. "Avicenna". Encyclopedia Iranica. http://www.iranica.com/articles/avicenna-iv. Retrieved 2010-04-14. 
  11. 11.0 11.1 Edward Grant, (1996), The foundations of modern science in the Middle Ages, page 30. Cambridge University Press
  12. 12.0 12.1 12.2 Auguste Schmolders, History of Arabian Philosophy in The eclectic magazine of foreign literature, science, and art, Volume 46. February 1859
  13. L.D. Reynolds and Nigel G. Wilson, Scribes and Scholars, Oxford, 1974, p. 106.
  14. C. H. Haskins, Renaissance of the Twelfth Century, p. 287. "more of Arabic science passed into Western Europe at the hands of Gerard of Cremona than in any other way."
  15. For a list of Gerard of Cremona's translations see: Edward Grant (1974) A Source Book in Medieval Science, (Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Pr.), pp. 35-8 or Charles Burnett, "The Coherence of the Arabic-Latin Translation Program in Toledo in the Twelfth Century," Science in Context, 14 (2001): at 249-288, at pp. 275-281.
  16. Biographisch-Bibliographisches Kirchenlexicon
  17. Edward Grant, A Source Book in Medieval Science, page 42 (1974). Harvard University Press
  18. Rubenstein, Richard E. Aristotle's Children: How Christians, Muslims, and Jews Rediscovered Ancient Wisdom and Illuminated the Middle Ages, page 215 (2004). Houghton Mifflin Harcourt
  19. 19.0 19.1 Albert the Great entry by Markus Fhrer in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  20. 20.0 20.1 20.2 Saint Thomas Aquinas entry by Ralph McInerny in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  21. For example, George E. McCarthy (ed.), Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth-Century German Social Theory and Classical Antiquity, Although many disagree Rowman & Littlefield, 1992.
  22. For example, Ted Sadler, Heidegger and Aristotle: The Question of Being, Athlone, 1996.
  23. For contrasting examples of this, see Hans-Georg Gadamer, The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy (trans. P. Christopher Smith), Yale University Press, 1986, and Lloyd P. Gerson, Aristotle and Other Platonists, Cornell University Press, 2005.
  24. Alasdair MacIntyre, 'An Interview with Giovanna Borradori', in Kelvin Knight (ed.), The MacIntyre Reader, Polity Press / University of Notre Dame Press, 1998, p. 264.
  25. Kelvin Knight, Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre, Polity Press, 2007.
  26. Fred D. Miller, Jr., Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle's Politics, Oxford University Press, 1997.
  27. Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics, Oxford University Press, 1999.

Further reading

External links